The Universe Speaks in Numbers Read online




  Copyright

  Copyright © 2019 by Graham Farmelo

  Cover design by Ann Kirchner

  Cover image copyright © Andrew J. Hanson, Indiana University

  Cover copyright © 2019 Hachette Book Group, Inc.

  Hachette Book Group supports the right to free expression and the value of copyright. The purpose of copyright is to encourage writers and artists to produce the creative works that enrich our culture.

  The scanning, uploading, and distribution of this book without permission is a theft of the author’s intellectual property. If you would like permission to use material from the book (other than for review purposes), please contact [email protected]. Thank you for your support of the author’s rights.

  Basic Books

  Hachette Book Group

  1290 Avenue of the Americas, New York, NY 10104

  www.basicbooks.com

  First Edition: May 2019

  Published by Basic Books, an imprint of Perseus Books, LLC, a subsidiary of Hachette Book Group, Inc. The Basic Books name and logo is a trademark of the Hachette Book Group.

  The Hachette Speakers Bureau provides a wide range of authors for speaking events. To find out more, go to www.hachettespeakersbureau.com or call (866) 376-6591.

  The publisher is not responsible for websites (or their content) that are not owned by the publisher.

  The Library of Congress has cataloged the hardcover edition as follows:

  Names: Farmelo, Graham, author.

  Title: The universe speaks in numbers : how modern math reveals nature’s deepest secrets / Graham Farmelo.

  Description: New York : Basic Books, [2019] | Includes bibliographical references and index.

  Identifiers: LCCN 2018053533 (print) | LCCN 2018060165 (ebook) | ISBN 9781541673922 (ebook) | ISBN 9780465056651 (hardcover)

  Subjects: LCSH: Mathematics—Methodology. | Physics—Philosophy. | Mathematical physics.

  Classification: LCC QC6 (ebook) | LCC QC6 .F3375 2019 (print) | DDC

  530.01—dc23

  LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2018053533

  ISBNs: 978-0-465-05665-1 (hardcover), 978-1-541-67392-2 (ebook)

  E3-20190410-JV-NF-ORI

  CONTENTS

  Cover

  Title Page

  Copyright

  Dedication

  Epigraph

  Prologue Listening to the Universe

  Chapter 1 Mathematics Drives Away the Cloud

  Chapter 2 Shining the Torch on Electricity and Magnetism

  Chapter 3 Shining the Torch on Gravity Again

  Chapter 4 Quantum Mathematics

  Chapter 5 The Long Divorce

  Chapter 6 Revolution

  Chapter 7 Bad Company?

  Chapter 8 Jokes and Magic Lead to the String

  Chapter 9 Strung Together

  Chapter 10 Thinking Their Way to the Millennium

  Chapter 11 Diamonds in the Rough

  Conclusion The Best Possible Times

  Acknowledgements

  Discover More

  About the Author

  Also by Graham Farmelo

  References

  Archives

  Notes

  Index

  To Claire, Simon, and Adam

  Explore book giveaways, sneak peeks, deals, and more.

  Tap here to learn more.

  The harmony of the world is made manifest in Form and Number, and the heart and soul and all the poetry of Natural Philosophy are embodied in the concept of mathematical beauty.

  —D’ARCY THOMPSON, ‘ON GROWTH AND FORM’ (1917)

  PROLOGUE

  LISTENING TO THE UNIVERSE

  I hold it to be true that pure thought can grasp reality, as the Ancients dreamed.

  —ALBERT EINSTEIN, ‘ON THE METHOD OF THEORETICAL PHYSICS’, 1933

  ‘Einstein is completely cuckoo’. That was how the cocky young Robert Oppenheimer described the world’s most famous scientist in early 1935, after visiting him in Princeton.1 Einstein had been trying for a decade to develop an ambitious new theory in ways that demonstrated, in the view of Oppenheimer and others, that the sage of Princeton had lost the plot. Einstein was virtually ignoring advances made in understanding matter on the smallest scale, using quantum theory. He was seeking an ambitious new theory, not in response to puzzling experimental discoveries, but as an intellectual exercise—using only his imagination, underpinned by mathematics. Although this approach was unpopular among his peers, he was pioneering a method similar to what some of his most distinguished successors are now using successfully at the frontiers of research.

  Oppenheimer and many other physicists at that time can hardly be blamed for believing that Einstein’s mathematical approach was doomed: for one thing, it seemed to contradict one of the principal lessons of the past 250 years of scientific research, namely that it is unwise to try to understand the workings of nature using pure thought, as Plato and other thinkers had believed. The conventional wisdom was that physicists should listen attentively to what the universe tells them about their theories, through the results of observations and experiments done in the real world. In that way, theorists can avoid deluding themselves into believing they know more about nature than they do.

  Einstein knew what he was doing, of course. From the early 1920s, he often commented that experience had taught him that a mathematical strategy was the best hope of making progress in his principal aim: to discover the most fundamental laws of nature. He told the young student Esther Salaman in 1925, ‘I want to know how God created this world. I’m not interested in this or that phenomenon, in the [properties] of this or that element. I want to know His thoughts, the rest are details.’2 In his view, ‘the supreme task of the physicist’ was to comprehend the order that underlies the workings of the entire cosmos—from the behaviour of the tiny particles jiggling around inside atoms to the convulsions of galaxies in outer space.3 The very fact that underneath the diversity and complexity of the universe is a relatively simple order was, in Einstein’s view, nothing short of a ‘miracle, or an eternal mystery’.4

  Mathematics has furnished an incomparably precise way of expressing this underlying order. Physicists and their predecessors have been able to discover universal laws—set out in mathematical language—that apply not only here and now on Earth but to everything everywhere, from the beginning of time to the furthest future. Theorists, including Einstein, who pursue this programme may be accused quite reasonably of overweening hubris, though not of a lack of ambition.

  The potential of mathematics to help discover new laws of nature became Einstein’s obsession. He first set out his mathematical approach to physics research in the spring of 1933, when he delivered a special lecture to a public audience in Oxford. Speaking quietly and confidently, he urged theoreticians not to try to discover fundamental laws simply by responding to new experimental findings—the orthodox method—but to take their inspiration from mathematics. This approach was so radical that it probably startled the physicists in his audience, though understandably no one dared to contradict him. He told them that he was practising what he was preaching, using a mathematical approach to combine his theory of gravity with the theory of electricity and magnetism. That goal could be achieved, he believed, by trying to predict its mathematical structure—the mathematics of the two theories were the most potent clues to a theory that unified them.

  As Einstein well knew, a mathematical strategy of this type would not work in most other scientific disciplines, because their theories are usually not framed in mathematical language. When Charles Darwin set out his theory of evolution by natural selection, for example, he used no mathematics
at all. Similarly, in the first description of the theory of continental drift, Alfred Wegener used only words. One potential shortcoming of such theories is that words can be treacherous—vague and subject to misinterpretation—whereas mathematical concepts are precise, well-defined, and amenable to logical and creative development. Einstein believed that these qualities were a boon to theoretical physicists, who should take full advantage of them. Few of his colleagues agreed—even his most ardent admirers scoffed. His acid-tongued friend Wolfgang Pauli went so far as to accuse him of giving up physics: ‘I should congratulate you (or should I say send condolences?) that you have switched to pure mathematics.… I will not provoke you to contradict me, in order not to delay the death of [your current] theory.’5 Brushing such comments aside, Einstein continued on his lonely path, though he had little to show for his labours: he had become the Don Quixote of modern physics.6 After he died in 1955, the consensus among leading physicists was that the abject failure of his approach had vindicated his critics, but this judgement has proved premature.

  Although Einstein was wrong to gloss over advances in theories of matter at the subatomic level, he was in one respect more far-sighted than his many detractors. In the mid-1970s, twenty years after he died, several prominent physicists were following in his footsteps, trying to use pure thought—bolstered by mathematics—to build on well-established but flawed theories. At that time, I was a greenhorn graduate student, wary of this cerebral strategy and pretty much convinced that it was perverse and heading nowhere. It seemed obvious to me that the best way forward for theorists was to be guided by experimental findings. That was the orthodox method, and it had worked a treat for the theorists who developed the modern theory of subatomic forces. Later known as the Standard Model of particle physics, it was a thing of wonder: based on only a few simple principles, it quickly superceded all previous attempts to describe the behaviour of subatomic particles. It accounted handsomely for the inner workings of every atom. What I did not fully appreciate at the time was how fortunate I was to be sitting in the back row of the stalls, watching an epic contemporary drama unfold.

  During those years, I remember attending dozens of seminars about exotic new theories that looked impressive but agreed only roughly with experiments. Yet their champions were obviously confident that they were on to something, partly because the theories featured interesting new mathematics. To me, this seemed a peculiar way of researching physics—I thought it much better to listen to what nature was telling us, not least because it never lies.

  I sensed a new wind was blowing and, as far as I could tell, it was going in an unappealingly mathematical direction. Privately, I expected the trend to peter out, but once again I was wrong. In the early 1980s, the wind gathered momentum, as the flow of new information from experiments on subatomic particles and forces slowed from a gush to a drip. For this reason, more theoreticians turned to pure reasoning, supplemented by mathematics. This led to a new approach to fundamental physics—string theory, which aspires to give a unified account of nature at the finest level by assuming that the basic constituents of the universe are not particles but tiny pieces of string. Theorists made progress with the theory but, despite a huge effort, they could not make a single prediction that experimenters could check. Sceptics like me began to believe that the theory would prove to be no more than mathematical science fiction.

  I found it striking, however, that many of the leading theoretical physicists were not discouraged by the glaring absence of direct experimental support. Time and again, they stressed the theory’s potential and also the marvellous breadth and depth of its connections to mathematics, many of which were revelatory even to world-class mathematicians. This richness helped to shift collaborations between theoretical physicists and mathematicians into an even higher gear, and generated a welter of mind-blowing results, especially for mathematicians. It was clearer than ever not only that mathematics is indispensable to physics, but also that physics is indispensable to mathematics.

  This intertwining of mathematics and physics seemed to exemplify the view expressed in the 1930s by the physicist Paul Dirac, sometimes described as ‘the theorist’s theorist’.7 He believed that fundamental physics advances through theories of increasing mathematical beauty.8 This trend convinced him—as ‘a matter of faith rather than of logic’—that physicists should always seek out examples of beautiful mathematics.9 It was easy to see why this credo had a special appeal for string experts: their theory had abundant mathematical beauty, so according to Dirac’s way of thinking, held commensurately huge promise.

  The ascendancy of string theory did much to give modern fundamental physics a strong mathematical hue. Michael Atiyah, a brilliant mathematician who had switched his focus to theoretical physics, later wrote provocatively of the ‘mathematical takeover of physics’.10 Some physicists, however, were dismayed to see many of their most talented colleagues working on recondite mathematical theories that in many cases were impossible to test. In 2014, the American experimenter Burton Richter bluntly summarised his anxieties about this trend: ‘It seems that theory may soon be based not on real experiments done in the real world, but on imaginary experiments, done inside the heads of theorists.’11 The consequences could be disastrous, he feared: ‘Theoreticians would have to draw their inspiration not from new observations but from mathematics. In my view, that would be the end of research into fundamental physics as we now know it.’

  Disenchantment with the state of modern theoretical physics has even become a public talking point. Over the past decade or so, several influential commentators have taken aim at string theory, describing it as ‘fairy tale physics’ and ‘not even wrong’, while a generation of theoretical physicists stand accused of being ‘lost in math’.12 It is now common to hear some critics in the media, especially in the blogosphere, complain that modern physics should get back on the straight and narrow path of real science.

  This view is misguided and unnecessarily pessimistic. In this book, I shall argue that today’s theoretical physicists are indeed taking a path that is entirely reasonable and extremely promising. For one thing, their approach draws logically and creatively on centuries of achievements all the way back to Isaac Newton. By setting out mathematical laws that describe motion and gravity, he did more than anyone else to construct the first mathematically based and experimentally verifiable framework for describing the real world. As he made clear, the long-term aim is to understand more and more about the universe in terms of fewer and fewer concepts.13 Leading theorists today pursue this agenda by standing squarely on the two granitic foundation stones of the twentieth century: Einstein’s basic theory of relativity, a modification of Newton’s view of space and time, and quantum mechanics, which describes the behaviour of matter on the smallest scale. No experiment has ever disproved either of the two theories, so they form an excellent basis for research.

  As Einstein often pointed out, quantum mechanics and the basic theory of relativity are devilishly difficult to meld. Physicists were eventually able to combine them into a theory that made impressively successful predictions, in one case agreeing with the corresponding experimental measurement to eleven decimal places.14 Nature seemed to be telling us loud and clear that it wanted both theories to be respected. Today’s theoretical physicists are building on that success, insisting that every new theory that aspires to be universal must be consistent with both basic relativity and quantum mechanics. This insistence led to consequences that nobody had foreseen: not only to new developments in physics—including string theory—but also to a host of links with state-of-the-art mathematics. It had never been clearer that physics and mathematics are braided: new concepts in fundamental physics shed light on new concepts in mathematics, and vice versa. It is for this reason that many leading physicists believe that they can learn not only from experiments but also from the mathematics that emerges when relativity and quantum mechanics are combined.

  The astonishing effective
ness of mathematics in physics has enthralled me since I was a schoolboy. I remember being surprised that the abstract techniques we learned in our mathematics lessons were perfectly suited to solving the problems we were tackling in physics classes. Most remarkable for me was that some of the mathematical equations that linked unknown quantities x and y also applied to observations that describe the real world, with x and y standing for quantities that experimenters could measure. It amazed me that a few simple principles, underpinned by mathematics we had only recently learned, could be used to predict accurately everything from the paths of golf balls to the trajectories of planets.

  As far as I recall, none of my schoolteachers commented on the way abstract mathematics lends itself to physics so exquisitely, one might even say miraculously.15 At university, I was even more impressed that theories that incorporated basic mathematics could describe so much about the real world—from the shapes of magnetic fields near current-carrying wires to the motion of particles inside atoms. It seemed something like a fact of scientific life that mathematics is utterly indispensable to physics. Only much later did I glimpse the other side of the story: that physics is indispensable to mathematics.

  One of my main aims in this book is to highlight how mathematics, as well as proving useful to physicists, has supplied invaluable clues about how the universe ticks. I begin with Newton’s epoch-making use of mathematics to set out and apply the law of gravity, which he repeatedly tested against observations and careful measurements. Next, I explain how the mathematical laws of electricity and magnetism were discovered in the nineteenth century, using a mathematical framework that had huge implications for our understanding of nature.

  I then move on to discuss two groundbreaking discoveries—first, basic relativity, and then quantum mechanics, the most revolutionary theory in physics for centuries. When Einstein used relativity to improve our understanding of gravity, he was forced to use mathematics that was new to him, and the success of this approach changed his view about the utility of advanced mathematics to physicists. Likewise, when physicists used quantum mechanics to understand matter, they were forced to use tranches of unfamiliar mathematics that changed their perspective on, for example, the behaviour of every one of nature’s smallest particles.